Banach-Tarski Paradox: Difference between revisions

From Optimal Transport Wiki
Jump to navigation Jump to search
No edit summary
 
Line 39: Line 39:


==The Banach-Tarski Paradox when <math> n=1\text {or } 2</math>==
==The Banach-Tarski Paradox when <math> n=1\text {or } 2</math>==
I quote a passage from Terrance Tao's personal website. <ref name="Tao">Terrance Tao,
I quote a passage from Terrance Tao's personal website. <ref name="Tao">  
   https://terrytao.wordpress.com/2009/01/08/245b-notes-2-amenability-the-ping-pong-lemma-and-the-banach-tarski-paradox-optional/#more-1354</ref>:
   https://terrytao.wordpress.com/2009/01/08/245b-notes-2-amenability-the-ping-pong-lemma-and-the-banach-tarski-paradox-optional/#more-1354</ref>:



Latest revision as of 03:51, 19 December 2020

Motivation

Recall that by Vitali's Theorem, there is no function satisfying all three of the following properties[1]:

  • is countably additive,
  • is translation invariant, and
  • for each interval , we have .

This result can easily be generalized to higher-dimensional Euclidean spaces.

To obtain a function that can reasonably "measure" Euclidean space, one might try to weaken some of the above properties. However, if we weaken only the requirement that be countably additive, namely by requiring that be merely finitely additive, we still run into problems in higher dimensions. The Banach-Tarski Paradox illustrates some of these problems.

The Banach-Tarski Paradox

In 1924, Stefan Banach and Alfred Tarski proved the following result[2]:

Let and be arbitrary bounded open sets in for . There exist and subsets of such that

  • the 's are disjoint and their union is ,
  • the 's are disjoint and their union is , and
  • for each , is congruent to , i.e. can be transformed into by translations, rotations, and reflections.

Hence, any function fails to satisfy the desired properties, because we can take two bounded open sets and that should have different measures (based on the fact that the measure of cubes is forced), split each of these two sets into pieces, then translate/rotate/reflect these pieces to match each other. Since the pieces of are congruent to the corresponding pieces of , these pieces should have the same measure, i.e. . By finite additivity of , this forces and to have the same measure, which contradicts our earlier assumption that and have different measures.

Rough Sketch of Proof for Special Case

The following is a rough sketch of how to decompose into two translated copies of plus a bit more using only translations and rotations. Without too much more trouble one could adapt this to eliminate the extra material, but we shall omit this for brevity and clarity.

Choose an angle which is incommensurable to . Let be rotation centered at the origin by counter-clockwise along the xy-plane. Let be rotation centered at the origin by counter-clockwise along the yz-plane. Let be the free group generated by and . We then can define a set M, using the axiom of choice, which selects one representative of each orbit defined by the action of on . Thus each point on is uniquely represented by a group element of and a point in . We then define , and , as a word, begins with for . Observe then that . We may then observe that and and . So by rotating three pieces of , we now have the pieces , which is more than sufficient to produce two copies of with translations. The argument extends to by instead of considering a point on , one considers the half-open line segment from the origin to . Then after some more work that needs to be done with the origin, one has more than doubled the unit sphere through rigid transformations.


Geometric Implications

The Banach-Tarski Paradox violates our geometric intuition of how volume is preserved when a physical object is broken into pieces and reassembled. Indeed, if the Banach-Tarski Paradox is to be believed, then it is possible to take a small ball (such as a pea); decompose the ball into finitely many pieces; move these pieces around in space via translations, rotations, and reflections; and reassemble these pieces into a new ball as large as the Sun. Of course, the ball may have to be decomposed into very strange pieces to accomplish this task.

One may note that the proof of the Banach-Tarski Paradox relies on the Axiom of Choice. Because of the many unintuitive implications of the Axiom of Choice, including the Banach-Tarski Paradox and the existence of unmeasurable subsets of Euclidean space, some mathematicians choose to reject the Axiom of Choice.

The Banach-Tarski Paradox when

I quote a passage from Terrance Tao's personal website. [3]:

"It is not possible to replicate the Banach-Tarski paradox in one or two dimensions; the unit intervals in or the unit disk in cannot be rearranged into two unit intervals or unit disks using only finitely many pieces, translations, and rotations, and indeed there do exist non-trivial finitely additive measures on these spaces. However, it is possible to obtain a Banach-Tarski type paradox in one or two dimensions using countably many such pieces; this rules out the possibility of extending Lebesgue measure to a countably additive translation invariant measure on all subsets of (or any higher-dimensional space).

References

  1. Gerald B. Folland, Real Analysis: Modern Techniques and Their Applications, Second Edition, §1.1
  2. Grzegorz Tomkowicz, Stan Wagon, The Banach-Tarski Paradox
  3. https://terrytao.wordpress.com/2009/01/08/245b-notes-2-amenability-the-ping-pong-lemma-and-the-banach-tarski-paradox-optional/#more-1354